Only One Word, Properly Altered Gandhi and the Question of the Prostitute
In the first Indian edition of his book, Hind Swaraj, Gandhi confessed that there was only one word that he would wish to alter: “prostitute”, an English translation of the word, ‘veshya’. In Hind Swaraj, Gandhi etched out his ideas for an India freed of British control and also makes a critique of modern civilisation with his emphasis on the “proper”. The book juxtaposes the connotations evoked by the prefix, ‘swa’, against that evoked by the image of the veshya, who is always at someone’s control and whose agency is perforce without. The use of these words served Gandhi well in seeking to enunciate his own beliefs regarding violence and domination. He breaks from the modern tradition that sees domination as the taking away of power and agency, and reconceptualises resistance as the recovery of resistance. It also questions domination by insisting on a subaltern responsibility for subordination; not as a loss of power, but the loss of swa.
AJAY SKARIA
I
In this use of the term veshya to describe Parliament, and in the later desire to alter it, two heterogeneous and even antithetical ways of thinking the swa or the proper clash. One of these ways
– the one that Gandhi most evidently affirms – is, in a sense that I will soon indicate, conservative: it is disturbed by the impropriety of the Parliament as veshya and seeks to re-establish a properly substantive order.
The other way (and why I describe it as Gandhi’s unthought will emerge) breaks with this conservative critique of “modern civilisation”, and stays with the question of the ownmost or proper nature of the proper. It is the insistent force of this question that makes Gandhi’s unthought press in so urgently on us today. In this essay, I shall be considering two registers of this question.
First, there is the register of violence. It is surely a striking feature of modern thought – or more precisely of the ontotheological tradition – that its concept of violence is that of abstraction from presence (and the even more impoverished statist one, derived from this concept, of violence as wrong measure). To the extent that the concept is inseparable from measure, violence is thought of as constitutive of the order of the concept. This is why the ontotheological tradition has often regarded measure itself as the primary violence. In its most explicit (and conservative) thinking of the swa,Hind Swaraj remains within this tradition. Here, violence is rejected by emphasising a constitutive and substantive separateness which is heterogeneous to measure and is therefore nonviolent. Yet on closer scrutiny, we will see, this separateness turns out to be founded on its own measure and violence.
This closer scrutiny, I will argue, also yields Hind Swaraj’s unthought – another thinking where the swa is marked not by a constitutive separateness but a constitutive separation produced by a giving without measure, where the swa is a separation which does not allow oneself to be constituted as one, as present. Concomitantly, violence (and not just the violence of colonialism) here comes to be thought not as measure that abstracts from substantive presence, but as the measure of what can only be given without measure, the swa or proper, as the measure which itself organises the ontotheological opposition of abstraction and presence.
Second, it would be very easy (and justified) to view Gandhi’s questioning of Parliament as produced by a conservative suspicion of representative democracy. But I would like to suggest that this questioning also, in its unthought, pushes the stakes of democratic thinking to a point where the name democracy is itself no longer appropriate. Trying to think an equality and empowerment of the people, democratic thinking – whether it proceeds to emphasise the majority, minority or the part that has no part – proceeds, as the suffix “cracy” suggests, within the thought of sovereignty.
Hind Swaraj, in contrast, insists on an equality and separation that cannot be subsumed under sovereignty. What would be a democratic politics that remains heterogeneous to democratic sovereignty? Would it even still go under the name democracy?
– this is another question raised by Gandhi’s insistence on the proper. Swaraj: this does not mean only the rule of the proper, it also asks questions about the proper of rule itself. Can this proper of rule be thought under the concept-suffix “cracy”? What is the violence that this concept-suffix practices? What would be a politics (if we can still call it a politics) that breaks with this concept-suffix?
Hind Swaraj reaches these questions because it breaks with the modern tradition of conceptualising domination as the taking away of power and agency, and of conceptualising resistance as the recovery of agency. Instead, it questions domination by insisting on a subaltern responsibility for subordination. Here, subordination is thought not as the loss of power but as the loss of the swa. A politics of resistance, such as that involved in satyagraha, attempts to redress this loss by staying in a constitutive separation, and by giving this separation also to the dominant. To trace this unthought of a subaltern responsibility for subordination – this is the most pressing concern of this paper.
Two more prefatory remarks on my mode of proceeding, both in this essay and in my other writings on the question of Gandhi. First, in fidelity to the distinctive subaltern responsibility that I pointed to above, I will be eliciting arguments from Hind Swaraj not to dismiss them, overcome them, or move beyond them, but rather to set them aside. That which is thus set aside, need it be said, is not nothing. Only that can be set aside which gives not only itself but more than itself, and is in this sense oriented towards what it is not, towards what is given from. It is against the finitude of that which thus sets itself aside that other arguments and positions can emerge. Conversely, it is only in emerging from this setting aside that these other arguments and positions can practice their distinctive responsibility.
Second, the arguments that I shall be developing turn crucially on issues of translation. Gandhi wrote almost all his major essays first in Gujarati, and then either himself translated them into English (as in the case of Hind Swaraj) or had his close associates do the translation under his supervision. But in Hind Swaraj as in other writings, the texts in the two languages diverge significantly from each other: entire words and phrases are missing in the English translation, or carry quite different connotations. These divergences cannot be adequately explained as caused by bad translation, or by the texts being addressed to different audiences. Rather, as I hope to indicate, they are symptomatic of a certain trembling in Gandhi’s text, where an unthought disrupts the conservative vocabulary which Gandhi’s critique of “modern civilisation” inhabits. It is by focusing on the gap between the English and the Gujarati texts (rather than by any attempt to produce a correct translation), then, that the arguments here are developed.6
I Not Restraint but ‘Thekaana’
Let me begin by considering, in order to set aside and apart, the conservative ordering of the swa. This ordering is signalled by the word ‘thekaana’. The editor says in chapter 5: “I said vaanjani (‘sterile woman’) because the Parliament has not till now, of its own, done a single good work. That it can do nothing if there is nobody putting pressure on it is its proper condition [sthithi svabhaavik riite; ‘natural condition’]”.7 A paradoxical formulation, thus: to not have a proper condition is the proper condition of the Parliament. The reader protests: “The word vaanjani does not yet apply to the Parliament. The Parliament is made of the people [‘lokoni baneli’], so it must doubtless work under the pressure of the people. This is its very quality, the ankush (restraint) on it”. But the editor insists: “It is not possible to see a single instance till now of Parliament taking even one thing [‘vastu’, ‘matter’] to its thekaaney [‘finality’]”.8
In this exchange between the reader and the editor, there emerges a distinction between the reader’s ‘ankush’ and the editor’s thekaana. The two come to name heterogeneous orderings of productivity and fertility.
Both these terms prove difficult for Gandhi to translate into English. There is simply no equivalent for the word ankush in the English sentence, which is truncated to only read: “This is its quality”. But ankush or restraint is distinctive as a quality: it is a force. Not only that, it is for the reader a legitimate force, a force that is not a violence, a force that produces swaraj or self-rule. This legitimacy is signalled by the genitive ‘ni’ (in the word lokoni, of the people), poised as it is between the two senses where people make the Parliament (thus perhaps Gandhi’s English translation, “by the people”), and where a transformation of the people makes the Parliament.
Furthermore, unlike Gandhi’s swaraj, the reader’s swaraj is not organised around the swa or the thekaana. In the reader’s conception, the Parliament cannot have a swa or proper that is independent of the people. It achieves its goals only under the restraint of the people, who are, as the genitive ni suggests, the true figures of fertility. For the reader, that the Parliament should be productive only under such restraint is its distinctive quality
– the quality which makes it more like a productive mother than a sterile woman.
Concomitantly, here the fertility and productivity of the people (and ministers) is constituted by their ability to be sovereign, without restraint. Elsewhere in Hind Swaraj, the editor remarks of the English people they “cannot stay at a thekaana” (‘thekaaneysar besi shakta nathi’; “are never steadfast”). But for the reader, it is precisely this refusal of a thekaana that constitutes the sovereignty of the people (or ministers and prime ministers). Indeed, as the sovereign subject who exercises restraint and knows no proper bounds, for whom boundaries and finitudes are contingent and fluid, the English people can only assert the irrelevance of the question of proper itself.
We need little reminder that such a rendering of boundaries (which is also the founding gesture of modern cosmopolitanism) has often been powerfully enabling. Over and again, this insistence on a sovereign subject has allowed a questioning of the conservative insistence on a substantive proper, whether that proper take the form of gender, class, caste or civilisational hierarchies.
Perhaps this is also indicative of the stakes for the reader of insisting on restraint: by producing the Parliament as a sovereign body that is nevertheless of the people (‘loko-ni’), it institutionalises that conception which takes democracy to be the sovereignty of the people. Ankush or restraint: condensed in this word is an argument that the democratic state embodies a force measured so correctly that it is not a violence, a force that because it represents the people need not be bound by any proper.9
For the reader, to reiterate, neither the people nor the Parliament has a swa – the former because their nature is to act, and the latter because its nature is to be acted upon. Through restraint, both a masculine and a feminine fertility and productivity outside the proper is affirmed – the Parliament as wife-mother, and the people or ministers as masters.
Against restraint, Gandhi develops the thought of thekaaney. Unlike ankush, this word is at least translated, though very unusually, as “finality”. Etymologically, thekaana is related to ‘sthaan’, place. A thekaana is a place that is a dwelling or home, including one within some hierarchy or order. A thekaana is not externally assigned; it is a destination that is a thing’s or being’s own. Objects cannot have a thekaana; only that can come home which has a proper.
It needs to be said right away that the editor’s insistence on things being governed by and brought to their thekaana is symptomatic of a conservatism. Here, the proper is elided into a thekaana thought substantively; furthermore, this substantive thekaana is presumed to be already inherent in the swa of the things themselves. Hence the disquiet about Parliament – for the editor, it raises the spectre of the rule of empty representation, one that does not have any proper in itself, and that takes its content from whatever the electorate or ministers gives it. Hence also the description of the Parliament as a veshya – the figure who has no thekaana and therefore no proper.
Nevertheless this conservatism provides, first, as I shall argue in the rest of this section, an initial critique of the violence involved in the representative democracy of ankush or restraint. Second, as I shall argue from the next section onwards, when we set aside the conservative thinking of the swa or proper through an insistence on the substantivity and separateness of the thekaana, there emerges another thinking of democracy whichHind Swaraj undertakes. This thinking is both initiated and repressed by the figure of the veshya. When this thinking is attended to, an abyssal distance opens up between the proper and the thekaana, such that the thekaana itself is interrogated, and it becomes of the nature of the proper to not reside in the proper and yet be oriented towards it, to raise questions about the proper as the manner of being oriented towards it.
To return, with this anticipation of later arguments, to the editor’s reserve about ankush. The editor questions, first, the productivity of Parliament (“[it] has not till now, of its own, done a single good work…”). To not do anything of its own – this is its ownmost condition. Furthermore, not doing anything of its own, it cannot take things (and a thing, we don’t need to be told, is not an object) to their thekaana. The converse of this argument would be that for Parliament to do a good work on its own would be to take things to their own place. Initiated here, in other words, is a thinking of a constitutive separateness. To insist on an own thekaana – this is to insist that true productivity would result in a constitutive separateness, where that which gives a thekaana separates from that which is given a thekaana.
Such separateness presumes an irreducible multiplicity which cannot be encountered through number. In number, separateness is rendered through the multiplicity of abstract equivalence, of homogeneous and interchangeable units. It is of the nature of the thekaana that it can never be homogenised this way, can only separate from itself only through and in a giving without measure, or a giving outside number. And yet, it is only through the multiplicity of number and equivalence that the basic categories of representative democracy (of which Parliament is the institutional apex) such as the electorate, or majority and minority, can be constituted. The insistence on separateness, thus, signals also profound reserve about representative democracy.
Second, the editor questions the sovereignty that the people exercise through restraint. For one, the sovereign of restraint, instead of recognising that things have their own thekaana and are therefore constitutively separate, asserts sovereignty over them and denies their separateness. Also, because the sovereign has no thekaana, this sovereignty is not truly sovereignty. Drawing on his English translation: “These people [the English] change their views frequently. It is said that they change them every seven years. These views swing like the pendulum of a clock and are never steadfast (‘thekaaneysar’). The people would follow a powerful orator or a man who gives them parties, receptions, etc.”
Lacking a thekaana that can constitute their separateness, the people and the ministers are here themselves mastered. “These Parliaments are a mark of the slavery of the people”.10 Not sovereigns, thus, but slaves: such an assertion would well describe the stakes of the critique of representative democracy that takes place here in the name of thekaana.
From the perspective of thekaana, it can now be ventured, the sovereignty exercised through the restraint of a democratic state is violent in the sense of disordering by taking from any place, by disrupting boundaries. In opposition to such sovereignty, thekaana is proposed as a force that is not violent – because it keeps things and beings at their own place, in their separateness. As such, the nonviolence claimed by thekaana is not that of a more correct measure, but that of not requiring measure: it is in this sense that it can claim to be a force on the other side of violence.
II Keeping as Control
The Exclusions of Thekaana
It is because of this conservative insistence on thekaana that the veshya and the sterile woman have to be rejected with such force. The sterile woman is not capable of playing a proper role as a fertile mother. And the veshya, even more constitutively than the “sterile woman”, is without thekaana. Unlike the sterile woman, whose proper orientation it is to not to be able to bring things to their thekaana, the veshya is the figure who as her ownmost orientation refuses a thekaana, and practices a mobility that is outside the thekaana.
But what is the thekaana that the veshya is outside?
This thekaana is embodied by the ‘dhani’ (a word that Gandhi usually translates as husband, but which is etymologically related to the sanskrit ‘dhan’ or “wealth” and carries connotations also of proprietor, owner, lord, possessor). Both the ministers and the prime minister are identified as the dhani in relation to the veshya: “And it is (‘like’) a veshya because which(ever) ministry keeps [‘raakhe’] it, it stays with [‘paase te rahe’] that ministry. Today its dhani is Asquith, tomorrow Balfour, and the next day a third”. And also:
It is appropriate that Parliament has been given the name of veshya. It does not have any dhani. It cannot have a one dhani. But the essence of what I am saying is not only this. When somebody does become its dhani – such as a prime minister – even then its gait is not steady [‘eksarkhi’]. Like a ruined veshya – so does Parliament always remain.11
And as indicated by the metaphor of enslavement that we encountered in an earlier passage, the “people” too retain the potential of being something other than slaves – they can become masters or dhani.12
Such, then, is the most evident ordering articulated in Hind Swaraj. In this economy, the veshya can only be a figure of ruin, necessarily kept outside every thekaana. Yet, though pushed to the margins, the veshya comes to ruin not just any particular thekaana but the thought of thekaana itself, most of all by raising questions about the violence that constitutes the separateness of the thekaana, or more precisely about the separation that the separateness that the thekaana must disallow. What emerges in attending to such questions is that the thought of thekaana cannot carry through the critique of representative democracy which it initiates.
We can begin attending to these questions by paying attention to one word, raakhe or keep (recall: “it is a veshya because which(ever) ministry keeps [‘jey pan raakhe’] it, it stays with [‘paase te rahe’] that ministry...”).13 The word can be used to describe the relationship of the dhani with both the veshya and the wife (‘dhaniyani’, or more usually, ‘baaydi’). (The phrase ‘baaydi raakhvi’, “keep a wife”, though no longer polite, was apparently common in at least central Gujarat till the mid-20th century.) The proper of the dhani, then, is thought primarily through keeping – the dhani keeps both the wife and the veshya.
Also, raakhe is related to ‘raakh’, ‘raakheli’ or ‘raakhel’– a courtesan, concubine or mistress. The root of raakh as of ‘raakhvu’: ‘raksha’ – protect, save or rescue (an English cognate?). Involved here, as this suggests, is a protecting that is a keeping outside, an exclusion. The raakhel is the figure who is protected only by the dhani, and who in this protection is excluded from legal institutions. Such exclusion is quite in contrast to the wife, who despite her subordination can in principle at least be the dhaniyani
– the wife as a female dhani. In this sense, the concubine stands as a figure of absolute subordination: kept only by the dhani, and incapable of being independent of the dhani. ‘Raakhvu’, then, is a distinctive kind of raksha or rescuing. As rescuing, it is a giving in the sense of patronage. But this giving of protection is not that of the gift: it is a keeping through domination. It is not surprising that, on two occasions, raakhe is translated as control, and that the English are described as keeping India.
Furthermore, the Parliament is not a veshya because it is kept, for one can be kept at one’s thekaana, as the wife is supposed to be. Rather, it is a veshya because it resists being kept any thekaana – unlike, say, the concubine or mistress. Resisting such keeping, the veshya moves from one thekaana to another (Asquith, Balfour and then a third), ruining these thekaaanas themselves.
For Gandhi, such promiscuity makes the Parliament as veshya incapable of separateness. Staying now with one and then with another, it nevertheless cannot give itself to that which it stays with because it does not have any thekaana (or consequently a swa) of its own, an itself to give. It can only in give the measure of interest (which measures the immeasurable) or the heat of passion (which unites with that which it is passionate about); and both these forms of giving do not allow for separateness. Giving in this way, without having an itself to give, the Parliament as veshya pulls the dhani into a measure and unicity that threatens the immeasurable separateness of the thekaana; it makes the dhani a weak master.
There are thus two ways of being outside the thekaana – those of the veshya and the weak master. Because her constitutive possibility raises the spectre of that which resists recuperation, because she threatens the dhani, the veshya is especially worrisome. Symptomatic of this is the attenuation that the word veshya already undergoes in Gandhi’s English translation. Here, the entire passage cited earlier (“It is appropriate…always remain”) is severely truncated: “Parliament is without a real master. Under the prime minister, its movement is not steady but it is buffeted about like a prostitute”.14
In this formulation, the focus shifts away from the veshya’s irrecuperability for any thekaana to the absence of a “real master”. Like the veshya, the weak master also cannot stay at thekaana; unlike the veshya, however, he is not constitutively without a thekaana, and can be brought back to the thekaana. The veshya is thus always potentially only the pretext for a focus on the weak dhani.
This shift from the veshya to a stress on the lack of mastery and masculinity is not exclusive to the English translation – recall that in the Gujarati text the people, ministers and prime ministers are all cast as weak masters. And the emphasis on a weak masculinity resurfaces in chapter 8, where the editor insists that the peace imposed by the English had made Indians ‘abada’ [“without strength”, also at the time a word for women], “emasculated, effeminate, and cowardly”.15
This lack of masculinity is especially significant since Hind Swaraj sometimes seems to suggest that only a real master can practise satyagraha. Rejecting in chapter 17 the reader’s suggestion that satyagraha is an appropriate weapon for “weak men [‘nabada manas’]”, the editor insists: “The strength and manliness that is required for satyagraha – that a cannon-force person can never have. Do you believe that a person without substance [‘namaal; maal’ – substance, ‘na’-not; ‘coward’] can ever violate a law that he dislikes”.16
Even the English are admirable to the extent that, in their masculinity, they keep England. Thus in chapter 7 the editor says about them “one thing” [‘ek vastu’; “one quality very strongly developed”]: they will not let their country “be lost” [‘java na de’]. “If any person were to cast an evil eye on it, they would make him stone-blind”.17 Here, ‘java..de’ or to lose is the inverse of raakhe or control. Only that which is possessed in the modality of raakhe as control can be lost in this sense.
In all of this, there emerges the precise sense in which the thekaana is conservative and substantive. Since a thekaana is constituted by control, to stay at a thekaana is necessarily to do a keeping, most evidently of other thekaanas but also of one’s own thekaana. The dhani, for example, stays at his thekaana by keeping his wife at her thekaana, and by excluding the veshya. Only through such a violent keeping in domination can the separateness of the thekaana be maintained. Thus, even thoughHind Swaraj intimates that thekaanas give each other their own separateness, this giving turns out to be founded on relations of domination, and in that sense a measured giving. Despite its profound commitment to a constitutive multiplicity beyond the abstract equivalence of parliamentary democracy, the thought of thekaana necessarily practises its own measured violence rather than being a force on the other side of violence.
The translation of thekaana as finality is symptomatic of this surreptitious violence. As a keeping or raakhe, a thekaana is indeed final. It is incapable of that radical giving which – to anticipate the argument below – loses the thekaana itself, which keeps itself only in this radical giving. And perhaps even the desire to alter the word veshya belonged to this violence of thekaana. Perhaps it was an effort (futile, of course) to banish the threat to the thekaana from that which constitutively resists recuperation. Perhaps by altering the word veshya, Gandhi sought to affirm the programme of converting the weak master into the strong master of thekaana in the sense of control.
If this effort to institute thekaana as control had been successful and “final”, then the alteration of the word veshya would have little to give us. It could not be set aside; it would have to be simply ignored as a minor quirk. But the alteration of the word veshya ruins the concept of thekaana, and in this ruining opens up other possibilities.
Indeed, raakhe as control or keeping is already explicitly questioned in Hind Swaraj. For though the keeping of England by the English is affirmed as “one quality very strongly developed”, there is a rejection of control itself as the mode in which Indians should keep India. Thus, when the reader suggests that “if they [the English] go, then I feel that we should keep [raakhiye] the constitution they created…”, the editor famously describes such government as “English rule without the Englishman”.
Hence the question that presses in on us: what is the relation between the veshya who rejects raakhe in the sense of “control”, and that editor who, rejecting the nationalist vision of the reader, also rejects raakhe as control, even when that control will keep Hindustan to its thekaana? And how would an alteration of the word veshya have altered this relation?
III Keeping as Letting Stay
Subaltern Responsibility for Subordination
To raise these questions is to open the possibility of thinking the swa otherwise than through the conservatism of thekaana; it is to think a proper that is heterogeneous to any thekaana or place. In order to pursue that possibility, consider the editor’s response in chapter 7 to the reader’s question of how the English could take India. The editor insists, “The English have not taken Hindustan, we have given it to them. They have not lasted in India on their own strength; we have kept [‘raakhya’] them”. “Hence it is more true to say that that we gave [‘aapyo’] Hindustan to the English than that Hindustan was lost [‘gayu’]”. When the reader asks, repeating the sense of raakhe as control: “Now tell me how the English could keep [raakhi] India”, the editor responds by multiplying the emphasis on the other sense of raakhe:
Just as we gave [it] to them, so do we let Hindustan stay with [‘paase raheva daiye’] them. Many amongst them say that theytook Hindustan by the sword, and they even say they keep it by the sword. Both these statements [‘vaat’] are wrong. In keeping [‘raakhvama’] Hindustan, the sword will be of little use; we alone let them stay [‘raheva daiye chhe’]. [Gandhi’s English translation: “The sword is entirely useless for holding India. We alone keep them”.]…So if we keep [raakhiye] the English in India, this is only for our self-interest.. To blame them is to perpetuate their power….we are the ones who help keep [‘raakhvama’] them.18
What is involved in raakhe in this second sense? A first clue could be this: Gandhi uses the English word “keep” to translate not only of raakhiye but also ‘raheva daiye’, “let stay”. But ‘daiye’ is also from ‘devu’, give. Here, to let stay also means to give staying. Raakhe in the second sense is to let stay or give staying
– but what is this?
To begin, what it is not. Let us start with the statement, “we have given it to them”. On too quick a reading of the editor’s reply, it would be easy to (mis)understand the giving or letting in this and other remarks in terms of agency – to think that the editor suggests that Indians were agential in their subordination, that it was not the greater power of the British which allowed them to take India. Rather, Indians let India be taken, even giving it to the British in exchange for material benefits. And Indians still “keep” the British in the sense that they continue to exercise agency in an undesirable manner – they operate only with the measure of self-interest, and let the British stay.
If the letting is indeed that of agency, then the reader and the editor share the same vocabulary. The only difference would be the minor one that where the reader blames the British, the editor more judiciously blames Indians themselves; that where the reader says that India was taken away by the British, the editor disagrees and says that India was taken by the British because Indians gave it quite freely. If this is so, furthermore, the editor’s argument could rightly be regarded as a precursor of that influential revisionist formulation in Indian historiography that has over the last few decades insisted that the colonised participated in their own colonisation, that India was ruled by the English because of support from significant sections of Indians.19
But the distinction which sets the terms of debate in the problematic of agency – that between taking what is given freely and taking away – is not tenable here. To begin with, it is simply not faithful to the text: the editor does not say that the British did not take India away; he says that they did not take India.
If we nevertheless habitually practise this very crude infidelity to the text, and do not even notice it, this is because to not do so makes his argument seem preposterous, even ridiculous. After all, he does also say that Indians gave India to the British. How can India not be taken by the British even though it has been given by Indians? How can India be given such that it cannot be taken even in giving? And in what sense do the British rule India if they have not even taken India when it was given to them?
But if, rather than dismissing these questions, we take seriously what they give, this allows us to encounter the force of the phrase “let stay”.
In the problematic of agency, the unstated assumption – regardless of whether the British took Hindustan by force, or Indians gave Hindustan to the English – is that Hindustan is an object. Only an object – that which we have a hold over – can be taken by force or taken and given in exchange. To give an object is simply to let go of it – which as remarked earlier is simply the inverse of raakhe as control.
But for the editor, Hindustan is not an object. This is the crux of his disagreement with the reader’s nationalism in chapter 9. For the reader, “because there are railways, today we see the spirit of one people [‘ek praja’, ‘new spirit of nationalism’] in Hindustan”. For the editor, however, “if there had been no railways, the English could not have such control over [‘kaabu’] Hindustan”.20 Furthermore, he insists that “the English have taught you that you were not one people [‘praja’, ‘nation’] before…[But] when the English were not in Hindustan, at that time [too] we were one people”. “One people does not mean that we had no differences between us; but our leading men would travel throughout India either on foot or bullock-carts, they would learn each others’ languages….”21
Contested here is the reader’s constructivist idea of Hindustan, where the railways create the abstract time and space within which nationalism can emerge, or Hindustan can be made into an object of desire. The editor’s hostility to the railways is because, enabling a control over the subcontinent, it facilitates and accelerates the making of Hindustan into an object.
What then is Hindustan for the editor? If we stress the suffix, Hindustan is a sthaan (etymologically associated also with thekaana) or place rather than an object. Furthermore, praja, the word that Gandhi here translates as “nation”, was earlier translated as “people”. Hindustan, then, is the thekaana of the praja or people.
Here, the tension between thekaana as control and as the home of the proper flares up. The swa is the ownmost. As such a thekaana, Hindustan always remains one’s own. As such a thekaana, can it be given or taken at all, and how?
When the editor says, “The English have not taken Hindustan, we have given it to them”, it is this question (rather than that of agency, where a measurably finite amount of responsibility
– the degrees of accountability of various actors in the conquest of India – is distributed) that he struggles with. “We have given it to them” – this giving is neither of the gift, nor that of exchange of objects. What then is this giving?
“We have given it to them”: here, the editor ventures a thought of raakhe (“we keep the English”) as a subaltern responsibility for subordination. Unlike agency, which, as the property of the agent, can be taken away, such subaltern responsibility cannot be taken away or lost. True, responsibility here concerns a loss, as the chapter’s title (‘Why Was India Lost’) intimates. But India has not been lost in the sense of being taken away. Because taking away involves measure, and because Hindustan is immeasurable, there is no circumstance in which the English can forcibly take Hindustan away from Indians – Hindustan can never be taken (though, as later discussion will suggest, it can be accepted as a gift). Through the term raakhiye, the editor tries to think a loss that is not a loss of agency (or of thekaana) but rather loss of responsibility – a subaltern responsibility for subordination.
Considered too quickly, this emphasis on a subaltern responsibility for subordination, and for the loss that such subordination necessarily entails, might seem an extremely dangerous move, a case of blaming the victim and exonerating the dominant. But this appears so only because in the commonsensical understanding (such as that of the reader in Hind Swaraj), responsibility is a measurably finite totality, where if one party is responsible, then the other is less so.
Yet that is far from being the case here. In this insistence on subaltern responsibility for subordination, the violence practised by the dominant and the subaltern are both infinitely greater. For the editor, the violence of “modern civilisation” is so great that, unlike the reader, he is not willing to countenance the continuation of any colonial institutions. Then again, while the reader sees colonial violence as a zero sum situation where the British have gained and Indians have lost, for the editor colonial violence is also directed at the English themselves. It has caused the latter too to lose their swa or themselves (because they too have in trying to take Hindustan resorted to a logic of measure; and perhaps even because they keep or control not just Hindustan but England itself). In a similar vein, while for the reader the loss of India can be redressed by taking back Hindustan, for the editor a taking back of Hindustan through violence would get nothing back.
(And, to point to an argument in Hind Swaraj that will not be elicted here, swaraj or the rule of the proper is possible only through a subaltern responsibility for subordination – and not through the dominant taking responsibility for domination. It is surely not accidental that it is when Gandhi effectively denies such subaltern responsibility – as he does often enough for women and dalits – that he also articulates some of his most conservative positions.22 Without such subaltern responsibility, the unilateral obligation of satyagraha would become impossible.23)
In the absence of any explicit discussion of subaltern responsibility for subordination in Hind Swaraj, we can elicit this concept only by being faithful to that essay’s unthought (which is always the ownmost of a thought, and perhaps never more so than when fidelity to the unthought involves betraying the thought).
Let us start once again with the remark, “we have given it to them”. If we understood this statement in the terms of thekaana, then we might say: Hindustan is a thekaana, and is characterised by having a swa. A thekaana cannot be given – the swa belongs to the thekaana in finality. “We have given it to them” – this means, “that which cannot and should not be given has been given”.
But what we are attempting to elicit here is not the problematic of thekaana, any more than it is that of agency. We are rather attempting to elicit that thinking which is thekaana’s own unthought. In this unthought, the swa not only can be given, but can exist only in this giving. As such, the argument here must be understood differently. The argument is not “that which cannot and should not be given and has been given”, but rather: the swa or proper has not been given in the manner proper to it.
To explicate this argument, let us consider two questions. To begin with: what is the manner of giving proper to the swa?
Very briefly, in anticipation of a more extended consideration on some other occasion, let me only insist for now on this axiom that organises Hind Swaraj’s unthought: that a giving proper to the swa involves, before anything else, the giving of separation itself. (It is this giving of separation that is arrested in the constative separateness of the thekaana.) This separation makes what is properly given into a gift.
We can think of this separation on two registers. First, there is what seems to be the separation of the giver from the receiver. But the other who is the receiver of the gift cannot be constituted empirically, and is always instituted through the separation that passes through oneself. Gifting is possible only as the other that one always is. (This is also why one can gift to oneself – because one is never only oneself. One cannot gift to oneself as oneself
– if such a contrary phrase may be momentarily entertained – cannot be gifted), to separate oneself from it is to let its proper or swa emerge (which is why the gift is the giver’s proper and more, thus revealing the productivity proper to the swa). As such, to not control the gift does not mean to put the gift at the disposal of the receiver (as though the gift were empty); it is to give the proper of the gift to the receiver.
Having indicated the two registers of separation that constitute the manner of giving proper to the swa, we can now turn to the second question: how does the giving proper to the swa differ from the raheva daiye or giving of staying that has occurred with the British?
The latter giving has to be thought, it seems to me, as a transformation (or more precisely, in another kind of fidelity to ‘sudhaara’, Hind Swaraj’s Gujarati term for “civilisation”, a reform) of the gift of separation that is proper to the swa. This re-form is what is questioned in the emphasis on the subaltern responsibility for subordination – on how “we keep the British”. Struggling with the relation between the two forms of giving,Hind Swaraj effectively produces an argument about violence: violence or re-form occurs when the proper, which can be given or taken only as a gift, without measure, has been given in measure. What is thus given in measure, however, can also be taken by the receiver only in measure.
To think violence in this manner is to set aside the conventionally radical perspective that understands domination and subordination primarily in terms of reason and power. What power acts on has to be thought not only empirically, in its objectness, but rather in terms of how this power re-forms the proper or swa. Without the swa, in other words, there can be no sustained thinking of violence. This is why “modern civilisation” cannot have a concept of violence that is anything more than a statism.
How or in what manner does this re-form act upon the gift, or on the giving without measure proper to the swa?
By not allowing the separations that constitute giving without measure. Indians seek to give Hindustan to the English in exchange. But Hindustan can be given in exchange only as an object
Thought in light of what has been argued above, does it not say this: Indians tried to give Hindustan as an object to the English. But Hindustan could not be separated out as an object from Indians, because it is their swa. Unable to separate themselves from the Hindustan that they give to the English, they give themselves to the English.Giving themselves to the English – this is how “we keep the English”.
A further question: who keeps – or, who is the “we” that is the subject of “keep”?
In a giving of oneself, no keeping as control is possible. In control, there is a oneself who stays apart from the giving, and does a keeping. In the giving of oneself all of oneself is given; here, the oneself who stays apart and keeps is annihilated. Therefore, if Indians give all of themselves, and still keep the British, then the oneself who is keeping can only be the swa – which cannot be given in exchange, and which stays distinct even in the giving of all.
But how or in what manner does the swa keep the English?
This keeping (which names nothing less than Gandhi’s unthought concept of subordination) occurs, paradoxically, in the losing of the swa. “We keep the English” – does not the phrase then say also this: we lose ourselves. Giving themselves to the English, giving in exchange what cannot be so given, the swa is lost (let us not forget that the title of the chapter in which this discussion occurs is, “Why was India lost”?). Indians lose their swa not in the sense that the English take it, but in the sense that they lose themselves by giving themselves without their swa.
To lose oneself: what this means is that the swa is separated from itself. We should not confuse this separation, which is the violence of “modern civilisation”, either with the separateness of thekaana or with the two other separations that have figured in the argument so far – the separation that sustains the gift, and the separation from power. Indeed, it is absolutely crucial to understand both the difference and the relation between these three separations.
To lose oneself: here the separation is from separation itself
– which is to say from the separation that sustains the proper gift. By giving in exchange that which cannot be so given, what is lost is precisely this separation that is constitutive of the gift. As such, this loss of oneself is abysally separated from the separation that founds the gift, where separation itself comes as a gift, where separation is not a loss.
To lose oneself: this separation is also separated, though in quite a different way, from the separation as loss invoked in the problematic of agency. In the latter, loss comes as a separation from power – as disempowerment and marginalisation. Put in the terms of the argument, “we lose ourselves”, we might say that the problematic of agency erroneously and in forgetting (and I will elsewhere return to this error-forgetting that Gandhi calls ‘bhool’) thinks of the separation as passing not through oneself but between oneself and what one gives of oneself as an object (and an object, recall, is defined by the logic of equivalence and can be possessed or controlled). Because of this error-forgetting, where Hindustan and “we” are converted into objects and subjects, the problematic of agency thinks of separation not as from separation itself, but from power. The argument “we lose ourselves” does not simply reject this agential problematic; rather, it sets this problematic aside as a forgetting, and thinks the loss more originarily as a separation from separation.
“We keep the English”: To insist on a loss that is of ourselves, of our swa – this is to insist on the primacy of the separation that passes through ourselves. As such, it is also to insist that we are always capable of being responsible for our subordination, our loss of ourselves. Where there is no proper, there can also be no such responsibility – there can at most be agency, which can be taken away. To be possessed by a swa that cannot be erased even when it is gifted or lost – such is the mark of the figure who is responsible for the letting involved in both the gift and its re-form.
“We lose ourselves” – this is a vertiginous thought, and in some formulations of Hind Swaraj, there is a drawing back from it. It is in this drawing back from Hind Swaraj’s own thought that the thekaana, with its constitutive exclusion of the veshya, is instituted.
In this drawing back emerges the distinction also between the veshya, the figure who has no swa, and the ‘dhani’, the figure who has lost his swa. In the violence of this insistence, however, what comes undone is nothing less than Hind Swaraj’s own thought of a subaltern responsibility for subordination. Central to that responsibility was the questioning of subordination through an insistence on the pervasiveness of a swa that even when lost remained one’s own. But the case of the veshya suggests that the swa is not pervasive. Lacking a swa, incapable of the separation that passes through oneself, the veshya is incapable of responsibility for subordination, and thus incapable of subalternity itself.
This exclusion authorises an immense violence against the veshya. For since violence is possible only against those with a swa, against those capable of the separation of gifting, no force used against those who lack a swa would be a violence. The veshya is excluded from the concept of violence itself – such is the violence practised on her.
This violence is conceptually underwritten by the opposition, evident in earlier passages, of the veshya’s “staying with” (the veshya stays with whoever/whichever) to “letting stay” (the dhani lets Hindustan stay with the British).24 But “staying with” can be opposed to “letting stay” only so long as the latter is thought through a substantive thekaana. When letting stay is thought as a loss of swa, as it is in the thought of a subaltern responsibility for subordination, then it is not only that opposition which crumbles. It is also the very concept of thekaana which crumbles, for the constitutive exception of the veshya which sustained that concept is no longer tenable.
An alteration of the word veshya – would it have concealed the ruin of thekaana, and the thought of a subaltern responsibility for subordination which emerges from that ruin?
IV The Question of Resistance
With the thought of a subaltern responsibility for subordination, of subordination as a loss of the proper, we have seen, the thekaana itself crumbles. This thought is heterogeneous both to the thekaana and to the veshya, but is given by the veshya’s ruin of the thekaana, by the emergence of the swa into the space left free by (and in) that ruin. This thought raises a new sheaf of questions. Most of all, there is this question: In the problematic of agency, subordination is resisted by seising power back. In the problematic of thekaana, it is resisted by bringing things and beings back to their thekaana. But how is subordination resisted in the thought of subaltern responsibility for subordination? Is satyagraha the name of that resistance? This question, which is given to us by the insistence on a subaltern responsibility for subordination, will have to be explored on another occasion.

Email: skari002@umn.edu
Notes
[This paper is an attempt to respond to some questions asked by students
1 The Gujarati text uses both ‘sudhaarva’ and ‘badalva’ to translate “alter”.
Collected Works of Mahatma Gandhi, second edition (henceforth CWMG)
Vol 18, p 69, May 28, 1919; Akshardeha (collected works in Gujarati)
Vol 15, p 317. All my citations of Hind Swaraj are to the editions published
as part of the English CWMG and the Gujarati Akshardeha. To help readers
working with other editions, I have usually indicated the relevant chapters too.
I provide citations to both the Gujarati and English texts, and unless
otherwise indicated I cite first from the language in which it was originally
written.
2 Hind Swaraj (henceforth HS), in Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 23; CWMG,
Vol 10, p 255. In cases where the writing was originally in Gujarati, as
with Hind Swaraj, I have provided my own translation. In cases where
there is a significant difference in translation, I have provided Gandhi’s
translation too. 3 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 23; CWMG, Vol 10, p 255. 4 Gandhi’s consistently translated ‘aadhunik sudhaara’ or ‘aajkaalnu
sudhaara’ as “modern civilisation”. But a more common meaning of sudhaara, then as now, would be reform. By the late 19th century, as now, sudhaara had overwhelmingly come to mean social reform, and one could be for or against sudhaara. In this essay, I will not explore Gandhi’s concept of “modern civilisation”, but it should be evident that the phrase cannot be understood here in its usual commonsensical sense.
5 Gandhi’s English translation goes: “That which you consider to be the Mother of Parliaments is like a sterile woman and a prostitute”. HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 23; CWMG, Vol 10, p 256.
6 A caveat too may be in order. What will and should be abundantly evident in what follows are the unavoidable traces of my obligations to the many thinkers who have written specifically on Gandhi, and those who have stayed with the questions that are the concern of this essay. But I have not explicitly footnoted these obligations for two reasons. First, such footnoting would involve a violence towards Gandhi’s thought, which would then be even more likely to be understood by analogy to these thinkers. Second, a responsible accounting of either my obligation to them or their thinking would require an engagement with these thinkers far more sustained than I can attempt within the limits of this essay.
7 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 23f, Hind Swaraj; CWMG, Vol 10, p 256.
8 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 24; CWMG, Vol 10, p 256. (CWMG: “It is not possible to recall a single instance in which finality can be predicted for its work”.)
9 The relation of human rights, so central to this conception of liberal democracy, to a thinking of the proper is too complex an issue for me to address here. But could it be that the concept of human rights is an attempt to produce, through the state, a conception of the human that can take the place of the swa?
10 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 28; CWMG, Vol 10, p 261.
11 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 24f; CWMG, Vol 10, p 256-57.
12 On too quick a reading of Gandhi’s writings, it might seem that the mother is an even more powerful organising thekaana than the dhani. Thus, even in the passage in HS (cf footnote 5), the veshya seems to be contrasted to the mother. And Gandhi did celebrate the mother as figure who exemplified love and suffering, even himself adopting that persona. Thus the title of Manu Gandhi’s autobiography– Bapu, My Mother. But motherhood as a political principle involved a male figure, the ‘brahmachari’ or celibate. It is surely not accidental that Gandhi insisted that it was his “celibacy” that allowed women to trust him and regard him as a mother. True, significant differences remain between Gandhi’s mother and the restrained mother of mainstream nationalism. The latter was pre-social and needed protection from the English. Gandhi’s mother, in contrast, is quite active: she has a thekaana and brings things to their proper places.
13 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 24f; CWMG, Vol 10, p 255.
14 HS, CWMG, Vol 10, p 257, cf the passage corresponding to footnote 11.
15 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 31; CWMG, Vol 10, p 266.
16 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 53; CWMG, Vol 10, p 294.
17 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 25; CWMG, Vol 10, p 258.
18 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 29; CWMG, Vol 10, p 263.
19 Both this revisionist formulation and most criticism of it is conducted within the problematic of agency. By insisting that the colonised participated in their own colonisation, by insisting on the miscibility of colonialism with both a precolonial past and with the colonised, the wound of colonialism is naturalised and denied, and colonialism is made an extension of what preceded it. (Because this mitigation of colonial domination stresses also the agency of the colonised, it has predictably found enthusiasts in a liberalising middle class India looking for a prehistory to Indian agency.) Conversely, many of those who fiercely attack such revisionist formulations understand the wound of colonialism as a loss of agency
– which, as I shall be suggesting, is not Gandhi’s argument. 20 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 32, Hind Swaraj; CWMG, Vol 10, p 267. 21 HS, Akshardeha, Vol 10, p 33; CWMG, Vol 10, p 268. 22 Gandhi was hostile to the idea of both women and dalits undertaking
satyagrahas against their subordination; he tried rather to bring about reforms amongst the dominant to redress their problems.
23 I discuss Gandhi’s category of obligation in “A politics without measure”, forthcoming in Manu Bhagwan (ed), The Dynamics of Diversity: Nationalism and the Politics of Identity in South Asia.
24 Cf the passages corresponding to footnotes 11 and 18.